guide:Ae227bcb0f: Difference between revisions

From Stochiki
No edit summary
 
No edit summary
 
Line 1: Line 1:
<div class="d-none"><math>
\newcommand{\mathds}{\mathbb}</math></div>
{{Alert-warning|This article was automatically generated from a tex file and may contain conversion errors. If permitted, you may login and edit this article to improve the conversion. }}
Getting back now to our general projective geometry program, we would like to have axiomatization and classification results for such quadruplets. In order to do this, following <ref name="bme">T. Banica and S. Mészáros, Uniqueness results for noncommutative spheres and projective spaces, ''Illinois J. Math.'' '''59''' (2015), 219--233.</ref>, we can axiomatize our various projective spaces, as follows:


{{defncard|label=|id=|A monomial projective space is a closed subset <math>P\subset P^{N-1}_+</math> obtained via relations of type
<math display="block">
p_{i_1i_2}\ldots p_{i_{k-1}i_k}=p_{i_{\sigma(1)}i_{\sigma(2)}}\ldots p_{i_{\sigma(k-1)}i_{\sigma(k)}},\ \forall (i_1,\ldots,i_k)\in\{1,\ldots,N\}^k
</math>
with <math>\sigma</math> ranging over a certain subset of <math>\bigcup_{k\in2\mathbb N}S_k</math>, which is stable under <math>\sigma\to|\sigma|</math>.}}
Observe the similarity with the corresponding monomiality notion for the spheres, from chapter 13. The only subtlety in the projective case is the stability under the operation <math>\sigma\to|\sigma|</math>, which in practice means that if the above relation associated to <math>\sigma</math> holds, then the following relation, associated to <math>|\sigma|</math>, must hold as well:
<math display="block">
p_{i_0i_1}\ldots p_{i_ki_{k+1}}=p_{i_0i_{\sigma(1)}}p_{i_{\sigma(2)}i_{\sigma(3)}}\ldots p_{i_{\sigma(k-2)}i_{\sigma(k-1)}}p_{i_{\sigma(k)}i_{k+1}}
</math>
As an illustration, the basic projective spaces are all monomial:
{{proofcard|Proposition|proposition-1|The <math>3</math> projective spaces are all monomial, with the permutations
<math display="block">
\xymatrix@R=10mm@C=8mm{\circ\ar@{-}[dr]&\circ\ar@{-}[dl]\\\circ&\circ}\qquad\ \qquad\ \qquad
\item[a]ymatrix@R=10mm@C=3mm{\circ\ar@{-}[drr]&\circ\ar@{-}[drr]&\circ\ar@{-}[dll]&\circ\ar@{-}[dll]\\\circ&\circ&\circ&\circ}
</math>
producing respectively the spaces <math>P^{N-1}_\mathbb R,P^{N-1}_\mathbb C</math>, and with no relation needed for <math>P^{N-1}_+</math>.
|We must divide the algebra <math>C(P^{N-1}_+)</math> by the relations associated to the diagrams in the statement, as well as those associated to their shifted versions, given by:
<math display="block">
\xymatrix@R=10mm@C=3mm{\circ\ar@{-}[d]&\circ\ar@{-}[dr]&\circ\ar@{-}[dl]&\circ\ar@{-}[d]\\\circ&\circ&\circ&\circ}
\qquad\ \qquad\ \qquad
\item[a]ymatrix@R=10mm@C=3mm{\circ\ar@{-}[d]&\circ\ar@{-}[drr]&\circ\ar@{-}[drr]&\circ\ar@{-}[dll]&\circ\ar@{-}[dll]&\circ\ar@{-}[d]\\\circ&\circ&\circ&\circ&\circ&\circ}
</math>
(1) The basic crossing, and its shifted version, produce the following relations:
<math display="block">
p_{ab}=p_{ba}
</math>
<math display="block">
p_{ab}p_{cd}=p_{ac}p_{bd}
</math>
Now by using these relations several times, we obtain the following formula:
<math display="block">
p_{ab}p_{cd}
=p_{ac}p_{bd}
=p_{ca}p_{db}
=p_{cd}p_{ab}
</math>
Thus, the space produced by the basic crossing is classical, <math>P\subset P^{N-1}_\mathbb C</math>. By using one more time the relations <math>p_{ab}=p_{ba}</math> we conclude that we have <math>P=P^{N-1}_\mathbb R</math>, as claimed.
(2) The fattened crossing, and its shifted version, produce the following relations:
<math display="block">
p_{ab}p_{cd}=p_{cd}p_{ab}
</math>
<math display="block">
p_{ab}p_{cd}p_{ef}=p_{ad}p_{eb}p_{cf}
</math>
The first relations tell us that the projective space must be classical, <math>P\subset P^{N-1}_\mathbb C</math>. Now observe that with <math>p_{ij}=z_i\bar{z}_j</math>, the second relations read:
<math display="block">
z_a\bar{z}_bz_c\bar{z}_dz_e\bar{z}_f=z_a\bar{z}_dz_e\bar{z}_bz_c\bar{z}_f
</math>
Since these relations are automatic, we have <math>P=P^{N-1}_\mathbb C</math>, and we are done.}}
Following <ref name="bme">T. Banica and S. Mészáros, Uniqueness results for noncommutative spheres and projective spaces, ''Illinois J. Math.'' '''59''' (2015), 219--233.</ref>, we can now formulate our classification result, as follows:
{{proofcard|Theorem|theorem-1|The basic projective spaces, namely
<math display="block">
P^{N-1}_\mathbb R\subset P^{N-1}_\mathbb C\subset P^{N-1}_+
</math>
are the only monomial ones.
|We follow the proof from the affine case. Let <math>\mathcal R_\sigma</math> be the collection of relations associated to a permutation <math>\sigma\in S_k</math> with <math>k\in 2\mathbb N</math>, as in Definition 15.11. We fix a monomial projective space <math>P\subset P^{N-1}_+</math>, and we associate to it subsets <math>G_k\subset S_k</math>, as follows:
<math display="block">
G_k=\begin{cases}
\{\sigma\in S_k|\mathcal R_\sigma\ {\rm hold\ over\ }P\}&(k\ {\rm even})\\
\{\sigma\in S_k|\mathcal R_{|\sigma}\ {\rm hold\ over\ }P\}&(k\ {\rm odd})
\end{cases}
</math>
As in the affine case, we obtain in this way a filtered group <math>G=(G_k)</math>, which is stable under removing outer strings, and under removing neighboring strings.  Thus the computations in chapter 13 apply, and show that we have only 3 possible situations, corresponding to the 3 projective spaces in Proposition 15.12.}}
Let us discuss now similar results for the projective quantum groups. Given a closed subgroup <math>G\subset O_N^+</math>, its projective version <math>G\to PG</math> is by definition given by the fact that <math>C(PG)\subset C(G)</math> is the subalgebra generated by the following variables:
<math display="block">
w_{ij,ab}=u_{ia}u_{jb}
</math>
In the classical case we recover in this way the usual projective version:
<math display="block">
PG=G/(G\cap\mathbb Z_2^N)
</math>
We have the following key result, from <ref name="bc+">T. Banica, J. Bichon, B. Collins and S. Curran, A maximality result for orthogonal quantum groups, ''Comm. Algebra'' '''41''' (2013), 656--665.</ref>:
{{proofcard|Theorem|theorem-2|The quantum group <math>O_N^*</math> is the unique intermediate easy quantum group <math>O_N\subset G\subset O_N^+</math>. Moreover, in the non-easy case, the following happen:
<ul><li> The group inclusion <math>\mathbb TO_N\subset U_N</math> is maximal.
</li>
<li> The group inclusion <math>PO_N\subset PU_N</math> is maximal.
</li>
<li> The quantum group inclusion <math>O_N\subset O_N^*</math> is maximal.
</li>
</ul>
|This is something discussed in chapters 9-10, the idea being that the first assertion comes by classifying the categories of pairings, and then:
(1) This can be obtained by using standard Lie group methods.
(2) This follows from (1), by taking projective versions.
(3) This follows from (2), via standard algebraic lifting results.}}
Our claim now is that, under suitable assumptions, <math>PU_N</math> is the only intermediate object <math>PO_N\subset G\subset PO_N^+</math>. In order to formulate a precise statement here, we first recall the following notion, from <ref name="bsp">T. Banica and R. Speicher, Liberation of orthogonal Lie groups, ''Adv. Math.'' '''222''' (2009), 1461--1501.</ref>, that we have already heavily used in this book:
{{defncard|label=|id=|A collection of sets <math>D=\bigsqcup_{k,l}D(k,l)</math> with
<math display="block">
D(k,l)\subset P(k,l)
</math>
is called a category of partitions when it has the following properties:
<ul><li> Stability under the horizontal concatenation, <math>(\pi,\sigma)\to[\pi\sigma]</math>.
</li>
<li> Stability under vertical concatenation <math>(\pi,\sigma)\to[^\sigma_\pi]</math>, with matching middle symbols.
</li>
<li> Stability under the upside-down turning <math>*</math>, with switching of colors, <math>\circ\leftrightarrow\bullet</math>.
</li>
<li> Each set <math>P(k,k)</math> contains the identity partition <math>||\ldots||</math>.
</li>
<li> The sets <math>P(\emptyset,\circ\bullet)</math> and <math>P(\emptyset,\bullet\circ)</math> both contain the semicircle <math>\cap</math>.
</li>
</ul>}}
The above definition is something inspired from the axioms of Tannakian categories, and going hand in hand with it is the following definition, also from <ref name="bsp">T. Banica and R. Speicher, Liberation of orthogonal Lie groups, ''Adv. Math.'' '''222''' (2009), 1461--1501.</ref>:
{{defncard|label=|id=|An intermediate compact quantum group
<math display="block">
O_N\subset G\subset O_N^+
</math>
is called easy when the corresponding Tannakian category
<math display="block">
span(NC_2(k,l))\subset Hom(u^{\otimes k},u^{\otimes l})\subset span(P_2(k,l))
</math>
comes via the following formula, using the standard <math>\pi\to T_\pi</math> construction,
<math display="block">
Hom(u^{\otimes k},u^{\otimes l})=span(D(k,l))
</math>
from a certain collection of sets of pairings <math>D=(D(k,l))</math>.}}
As explained in <ref name="bsp">T. Banica and R. Speicher, Liberation of orthogonal Lie groups, ''Adv. Math.'' '''222''' (2009), 1461--1501.</ref>, by “saturating” the sets <math>D(k,l)</math>, we can assume that the collection <math>D=(D(k,l))</math> is a category of pairings, in the sense that it is stable under vertical and horizontal concatenation, upside-down turning, and contains the semicircle.
In the projective case now, following <ref name="bme">T. Banica and S. Mészáros, Uniqueness results for noncommutative spheres and projective spaces, ''Illinois J. Math.'' '''59''' (2015), 219--233.</ref>, let us formulate:
{{defncard|label=|id=|A projective category of pairings is a collection of subsets
<math display="block">
NC_2(2k,2l)\subset E(k,l)\subset P_2(2k,2l)
</math>
stable under the usual categorical operations, and satisfying <math>\sigma\in E\implies |\sigma|\in E</math>.}}
As basic examples here, we have the following projective categories of pairings, where <math>P_2^*</math> is the category of matching pairings:
<math display="block">
NC_2\subset P_2^*\subset P_2
</math>
This follows indeed from definitions. Now with the above notion in hand, we can formulate the following projective analogue of the notion of easiness:
{{defncard|label=|id=|An intermediate compact quantum group
<math display="block">
PO_N\subset H\subset PO_N^+
</math>
is called projectively easy when its Tannakian category
<math display="block">
span(NC_2(2k,2l))\subset Hom(v^{\otimes k},v^{\otimes l})\subset span(P_2(2k,2l))
</math>
comes via via the following formula, using the standard <math>\pi\to T_\pi</math> construction,
<math display="block">
Hom(v^{\otimes k},v^{\otimes l})=span(E(k,l))
</math>
for a certain projective category of pairings <math>E=(E(k,l))</math>.}}
Thus, we have a projective notion of easiness. Observe that, given an easy quantum group <math>O_N\subset G\subset O_N^+</math>, its projective version <math>PO_N\subset PG\subset PO_N^+</math> is projectively easy in our sense. In particular the basic projective quantum groups <math>PO_N\subset PU_N\subset PO_N^+</math> are all projectively easy in our sense, coming from the categories <math>NC_2\subset P_2^*\subset P_2</math>.
We have in fact the following general result, from <ref name="bme">T. Banica and S. Mészáros, Uniqueness results for noncommutative spheres and projective spaces, ''Illinois J. Math.'' '''59''' (2015), 219--233.</ref>:
{{proofcard|Theorem|theorem-3|We have a bijective correspondence between the affine and projective categories of partitions, given by the operation
<math display="block">
G\to PG
</math>
at the level of the corresponding affine and projective easy quantum groups.
|The construction of correspondence <math>D\to E</math> is clear, simply by setting:
<math display="block">
E(k,l)=D(2k,2l)
</math>
Indeed, due to the axioms in Definition 15.15, the conditions in Definition 15.17 are satisfied. Conversely, given <math>E=(E(k,l))</math> as in Definition 15.17, we can set:
<math display="block">
D(k,l)=\begin{cases}
E(k,l)&(k,l\ {\rm even})\\
\{\sigma:|\sigma\in E(k+1,l+1)\}&(k,l\ {\rm odd})
\end{cases}
</math>
Our claim is that <math>D=(D(k,l))</math> is a category of partitions. Indeed:
(1) The composition action is clear. Indeed, when looking at the numbers of legs involved, in the even case this is clear, and in the odd case, this follows from:
<math display="block">
\begin{eqnarray*}
|\sigma,|\sigma'\in E
&\implies&|^\sigma_\tau\in E\\
&\implies&{\ }^\sigma_\tau\in D
\end{eqnarray*}
</math>
(2) For the tensor product axiom, we have 4 cases to be investigated, depending on the parity of the number of legs of <math>\sigma,\tau</math>, as follows:
-- The even/even case is clear.
-- The odd/even case follows from the following computation:
<math display="block">
\begin{eqnarray*}
|\sigma,\tau\in E
&\implies&|\sigma\tau\in E\\
&\implies&\sigma\tau\in D
\end{eqnarray*}
</math>
-- Regarding now the even/odd case, this can be solved as follows:
<math display="block">
\begin{eqnarray*}
\sigma,|\tau\in E
&\implies&|\sigma|,|\tau\in E\\
&\implies&|\sigma||\tau\in E\\
&\implies&|\sigma\tau\in E\\
&\implies&\sigma\tau\in D
\end{eqnarray*}
</math>
-- As for the remaining odd/odd case, here the computation is as follows:
<math display="block">
\begin{eqnarray*}
|\sigma,|\tau\in E
&\implies&||\sigma|,|\tau\in E\\
&\implies&||\sigma||\tau\in E\\
&\implies&\sigma\tau\in E\\
&\implies&\sigma\tau\in D
\end{eqnarray*}
</math>
(3) Finally, the conjugation axiom is clear from definitions. It is also clear that both compositions <math>D\to E\to D</math> and <math>E\to D\to E</math> are the identities, as claimed. As for the quantum group assertion, this is clear as well from definitions.}}
Now back to uniqueness issues, we have here the following result, also from <ref name="bme">T. Banica and S. Mészáros, Uniqueness results for noncommutative spheres and projective spaces, ''Illinois J. Math.'' '''59''' (2015), 219--233.</ref>:
{{proofcard|Theorem|theorem-4|We have the following results:
<ul><li> <math>O_N^*</math> is the only intermediate easy quantum group, as follows:
<math display="block">
O_N\subset G\subset O_N^+
</math>
</li>
<li> <math>PU_N</math> is the only intermediate projectively easy quantum group, as follows:
<math display="block">
PO_N\subset G\subset PO_N^+
</math>
</li>
</ul>
|The idea here is as follows:
(1) The assertion regarding <math>O_N\subset O_N^*\subset O_N^+</math> is from <ref name="bc+">T. Banica, J. Bichon, B. Collins and S. Curran, A maximality result for orthogonal quantum groups, ''Comm. Algebra'' '''41''' (2013), 656--665.</ref>, and this is something that we already know, explained in chapter 9.
(2) The assertion regarding <math>PO_N\subset PU_N\subset PO_N^+</math> follows from the classification result in (1), and from the duality in Theorem 15.19.}}
Summarizing, we have analogues of the various affine classification results, with the remark that everything becomes simpler in the projective setting.
==General references==
{{cite arXiv|last1=Banica|first1=Teo|year=2024|title=Affine noncommutative geometry|eprint=2012.10973|class=math.QA}}
==References==
{{reflist}}

Latest revision as of 20:41, 22 April 2025

[math] \newcommand{\mathds}{\mathbb}[/math]

This article was automatically generated from a tex file and may contain conversion errors. If permitted, you may login and edit this article to improve the conversion.

Getting back now to our general projective geometry program, we would like to have axiomatization and classification results for such quadruplets. In order to do this, following [1], we can axiomatize our various projective spaces, as follows:

Definition

A monomial projective space is a closed subset [math]P\subset P^{N-1}_+[/math] obtained via relations of type

[[math]] p_{i_1i_2}\ldots p_{i_{k-1}i_k}=p_{i_{\sigma(1)}i_{\sigma(2)}}\ldots p_{i_{\sigma(k-1)}i_{\sigma(k)}},\ \forall (i_1,\ldots,i_k)\in\{1,\ldots,N\}^k [[/math]]
with [math]\sigma[/math] ranging over a certain subset of [math]\bigcup_{k\in2\mathbb N}S_k[/math], which is stable under [math]\sigma\to|\sigma|[/math].

Observe the similarity with the corresponding monomiality notion for the spheres, from chapter 13. The only subtlety in the projective case is the stability under the operation [math]\sigma\to|\sigma|[/math], which in practice means that if the above relation associated to [math]\sigma[/math] holds, then the following relation, associated to [math]|\sigma|[/math], must hold as well:

[[math]] p_{i_0i_1}\ldots p_{i_ki_{k+1}}=p_{i_0i_{\sigma(1)}}p_{i_{\sigma(2)}i_{\sigma(3)}}\ldots p_{i_{\sigma(k-2)}i_{\sigma(k-1)}}p_{i_{\sigma(k)}i_{k+1}} [[/math]]


As an illustration, the basic projective spaces are all monomial:

Proposition

The [math]3[/math] projective spaces are all monomial, with the permutations

[[math]] \xymatrix@R=10mm@C=8mm{\circ\ar@{-}[dr]&\circ\ar@{-}[dl]\\\circ&\circ}\qquad\ \qquad\ \qquad \item[a]ymatrix@R=10mm@C=3mm{\circ\ar@{-}[drr]&\circ\ar@{-}[drr]&\circ\ar@{-}[dll]&\circ\ar@{-}[dll]\\\circ&\circ&\circ&\circ} [[/math]]
producing respectively the spaces [math]P^{N-1}_\mathbb R,P^{N-1}_\mathbb C[/math], and with no relation needed for [math]P^{N-1}_+[/math].


Show Proof

We must divide the algebra [math]C(P^{N-1}_+)[/math] by the relations associated to the diagrams in the statement, as well as those associated to their shifted versions, given by:

[[math]] \xymatrix@R=10mm@C=3mm{\circ\ar@{-}[d]&\circ\ar@{-}[dr]&\circ\ar@{-}[dl]&\circ\ar@{-}[d]\\\circ&\circ&\circ&\circ} \qquad\ \qquad\ \qquad \item[a]ymatrix@R=10mm@C=3mm{\circ\ar@{-}[d]&\circ\ar@{-}[drr]&\circ\ar@{-}[drr]&\circ\ar@{-}[dll]&\circ\ar@{-}[dll]&\circ\ar@{-}[d]\\\circ&\circ&\circ&\circ&\circ&\circ} [[/math]]

(1) The basic crossing, and its shifted version, produce the following relations:

[[math]] p_{ab}=p_{ba} [[/math]]

[[math]] p_{ab}p_{cd}=p_{ac}p_{bd} [[/math]]


Now by using these relations several times, we obtain the following formula:

[[math]] p_{ab}p_{cd} =p_{ac}p_{bd} =p_{ca}p_{db} =p_{cd}p_{ab} [[/math]]


Thus, the space produced by the basic crossing is classical, [math]P\subset P^{N-1}_\mathbb C[/math]. By using one more time the relations [math]p_{ab}=p_{ba}[/math] we conclude that we have [math]P=P^{N-1}_\mathbb R[/math], as claimed.


(2) The fattened crossing, and its shifted version, produce the following relations:

[[math]] p_{ab}p_{cd}=p_{cd}p_{ab} [[/math]]

[[math]] p_{ab}p_{cd}p_{ef}=p_{ad}p_{eb}p_{cf} [[/math]]


The first relations tell us that the projective space must be classical, [math]P\subset P^{N-1}_\mathbb C[/math]. Now observe that with [math]p_{ij}=z_i\bar{z}_j[/math], the second relations read:

[[math]] z_a\bar{z}_bz_c\bar{z}_dz_e\bar{z}_f=z_a\bar{z}_dz_e\bar{z}_bz_c\bar{z}_f [[/math]]


Since these relations are automatic, we have [math]P=P^{N-1}_\mathbb C[/math], and we are done.

Following [1], we can now formulate our classification result, as follows:

Theorem

The basic projective spaces, namely

[[math]] P^{N-1}_\mathbb R\subset P^{N-1}_\mathbb C\subset P^{N-1}_+ [[/math]]
are the only monomial ones.


Show Proof

We follow the proof from the affine case. Let [math]\mathcal R_\sigma[/math] be the collection of relations associated to a permutation [math]\sigma\in S_k[/math] with [math]k\in 2\mathbb N[/math], as in Definition 15.11. We fix a monomial projective space [math]P\subset P^{N-1}_+[/math], and we associate to it subsets [math]G_k\subset S_k[/math], as follows:

[[math]] G_k=\begin{cases} \{\sigma\in S_k|\mathcal R_\sigma\ {\rm hold\ over\ }P\}&(k\ {\rm even})\\ \{\sigma\in S_k|\mathcal R_{|\sigma}\ {\rm hold\ over\ }P\}&(k\ {\rm odd}) \end{cases} [[/math]]


As in the affine case, we obtain in this way a filtered group [math]G=(G_k)[/math], which is stable under removing outer strings, and under removing neighboring strings. Thus the computations in chapter 13 apply, and show that we have only 3 possible situations, corresponding to the 3 projective spaces in Proposition 15.12.

Let us discuss now similar results for the projective quantum groups. Given a closed subgroup [math]G\subset O_N^+[/math], its projective version [math]G\to PG[/math] is by definition given by the fact that [math]C(PG)\subset C(G)[/math] is the subalgebra generated by the following variables:

[[math]] w_{ij,ab}=u_{ia}u_{jb} [[/math]]


In the classical case we recover in this way the usual projective version:

[[math]] PG=G/(G\cap\mathbb Z_2^N) [[/math]]


We have the following key result, from [2]:

Theorem

The quantum group [math]O_N^*[/math] is the unique intermediate easy quantum group [math]O_N\subset G\subset O_N^+[/math]. Moreover, in the non-easy case, the following happen:

  • The group inclusion [math]\mathbb TO_N\subset U_N[/math] is maximal.
  • The group inclusion [math]PO_N\subset PU_N[/math] is maximal.
  • The quantum group inclusion [math]O_N\subset O_N^*[/math] is maximal.


Show Proof

This is something discussed in chapters 9-10, the idea being that the first assertion comes by classifying the categories of pairings, and then:


(1) This can be obtained by using standard Lie group methods.


(2) This follows from (1), by taking projective versions.


(3) This follows from (2), via standard algebraic lifting results.

Our claim now is that, under suitable assumptions, [math]PU_N[/math] is the only intermediate object [math]PO_N\subset G\subset PO_N^+[/math]. In order to formulate a precise statement here, we first recall the following notion, from [3], that we have already heavily used in this book:

Definition

A collection of sets [math]D=\bigsqcup_{k,l}D(k,l)[/math] with

[[math]] D(k,l)\subset P(k,l) [[/math]]
is called a category of partitions when it has the following properties:

  • Stability under the horizontal concatenation, [math](\pi,\sigma)\to[\pi\sigma][/math].
  • Stability under vertical concatenation [math](\pi,\sigma)\to[^\sigma_\pi][/math], with matching middle symbols.
  • Stability under the upside-down turning [math]*[/math], with switching of colors, [math]\circ\leftrightarrow\bullet[/math].
  • Each set [math]P(k,k)[/math] contains the identity partition [math]||\ldots||[/math].
  • The sets [math]P(\emptyset,\circ\bullet)[/math] and [math]P(\emptyset,\bullet\circ)[/math] both contain the semicircle [math]\cap[/math].

The above definition is something inspired from the axioms of Tannakian categories, and going hand in hand with it is the following definition, also from [3]:

Definition

An intermediate compact quantum group

[[math]] O_N\subset G\subset O_N^+ [[/math]]
is called easy when the corresponding Tannakian category

[[math]] span(NC_2(k,l))\subset Hom(u^{\otimes k},u^{\otimes l})\subset span(P_2(k,l)) [[/math]]
comes via the following formula, using the standard [math]\pi\to T_\pi[/math] construction,

[[math]] Hom(u^{\otimes k},u^{\otimes l})=span(D(k,l)) [[/math]]
from a certain collection of sets of pairings [math]D=(D(k,l))[/math].

As explained in [3], by “saturating” the sets [math]D(k,l)[/math], we can assume that the collection [math]D=(D(k,l))[/math] is a category of pairings, in the sense that it is stable under vertical and horizontal concatenation, upside-down turning, and contains the semicircle.


In the projective case now, following [1], let us formulate:

Definition

A projective category of pairings is a collection of subsets

[[math]] NC_2(2k,2l)\subset E(k,l)\subset P_2(2k,2l) [[/math]]
stable under the usual categorical operations, and satisfying [math]\sigma\in E\implies |\sigma|\in E[/math].

As basic examples here, we have the following projective categories of pairings, where [math]P_2^*[/math] is the category of matching pairings:

[[math]] NC_2\subset P_2^*\subset P_2 [[/math]]


This follows indeed from definitions. Now with the above notion in hand, we can formulate the following projective analogue of the notion of easiness:

Definition

An intermediate compact quantum group

[[math]] PO_N\subset H\subset PO_N^+ [[/math]]
is called projectively easy when its Tannakian category

[[math]] span(NC_2(2k,2l))\subset Hom(v^{\otimes k},v^{\otimes l})\subset span(P_2(2k,2l)) [[/math]]
comes via via the following formula, using the standard [math]\pi\to T_\pi[/math] construction,

[[math]] Hom(v^{\otimes k},v^{\otimes l})=span(E(k,l)) [[/math]]
for a certain projective category of pairings [math]E=(E(k,l))[/math].

Thus, we have a projective notion of easiness. Observe that, given an easy quantum group [math]O_N\subset G\subset O_N^+[/math], its projective version [math]PO_N\subset PG\subset PO_N^+[/math] is projectively easy in our sense. In particular the basic projective quantum groups [math]PO_N\subset PU_N\subset PO_N^+[/math] are all projectively easy in our sense, coming from the categories [math]NC_2\subset P_2^*\subset P_2[/math].


We have in fact the following general result, from [1]:

Theorem

We have a bijective correspondence between the affine and projective categories of partitions, given by the operation

[[math]] G\to PG [[/math]]

at the level of the corresponding affine and projective easy quantum groups.


Show Proof

The construction of correspondence [math]D\to E[/math] is clear, simply by setting:

[[math]] E(k,l)=D(2k,2l) [[/math]]


Indeed, due to the axioms in Definition 15.15, the conditions in Definition 15.17 are satisfied. Conversely, given [math]E=(E(k,l))[/math] as in Definition 15.17, we can set:

[[math]] D(k,l)=\begin{cases} E(k,l)&(k,l\ {\rm even})\\ \{\sigma:|\sigma\in E(k+1,l+1)\}&(k,l\ {\rm odd}) \end{cases} [[/math]]


Our claim is that [math]D=(D(k,l))[/math] is a category of partitions. Indeed:


(1) The composition action is clear. Indeed, when looking at the numbers of legs involved, in the even case this is clear, and in the odd case, this follows from:

[[math]] \begin{eqnarray*} |\sigma,|\sigma'\in E &\implies&|^\sigma_\tau\in E\\ &\implies&{\ }^\sigma_\tau\in D \end{eqnarray*} [[/math]]


(2) For the tensor product axiom, we have 4 cases to be investigated, depending on the parity of the number of legs of [math]\sigma,\tau[/math], as follows:


-- The even/even case is clear.


-- The odd/even case follows from the following computation:

[[math]] \begin{eqnarray*} |\sigma,\tau\in E &\implies&|\sigma\tau\in E\\ &\implies&\sigma\tau\in D \end{eqnarray*} [[/math]]


-- Regarding now the even/odd case, this can be solved as follows:

[[math]] \begin{eqnarray*} \sigma,|\tau\in E &\implies&|\sigma|,|\tau\in E\\ &\implies&|\sigma||\tau\in E\\ &\implies&|\sigma\tau\in E\\ &\implies&\sigma\tau\in D \end{eqnarray*} [[/math]]


-- As for the remaining odd/odd case, here the computation is as follows:

[[math]] \begin{eqnarray*} |\sigma,|\tau\in E &\implies&||\sigma|,|\tau\in E\\ &\implies&||\sigma||\tau\in E\\ &\implies&\sigma\tau\in E\\ &\implies&\sigma\tau\in D \end{eqnarray*} [[/math]]


(3) Finally, the conjugation axiom is clear from definitions. It is also clear that both compositions [math]D\to E\to D[/math] and [math]E\to D\to E[/math] are the identities, as claimed. As for the quantum group assertion, this is clear as well from definitions.

Now back to uniqueness issues, we have here the following result, also from [1]:

Theorem

We have the following results:

  • [math]O_N^*[/math] is the only intermediate easy quantum group, as follows:
    [[math]] O_N\subset G\subset O_N^+ [[/math]]
  • [math]PU_N[/math] is the only intermediate projectively easy quantum group, as follows:
    [[math]] PO_N\subset G\subset PO_N^+ [[/math]]


Show Proof

The idea here is as follows:


(1) The assertion regarding [math]O_N\subset O_N^*\subset O_N^+[/math] is from [2], and this is something that we already know, explained in chapter 9.


(2) The assertion regarding [math]PO_N\subset PU_N\subset PO_N^+[/math] follows from the classification result in (1), and from the duality in Theorem 15.19.

Summarizing, we have analogues of the various affine classification results, with the remark that everything becomes simpler in the projective setting.

General references

Banica, Teo (2024). "Affine noncommutative geometry". arXiv:2012.10973 [math.QA].

References

  1. 1.0 1.1 1.2 1.3 1.4 T. Banica and S. Mészáros, Uniqueness results for noncommutative spheres and projective spaces, Illinois J. Math. 59 (2015), 219--233.
  2. 2.0 2.1 T. Banica, J. Bichon, B. Collins and S. Curran, A maximality result for orthogonal quantum groups, Comm. Algebra 41 (2013), 656--665.
  3. 3.0 3.1 3.2 T. Banica and R. Speicher, Liberation of orthogonal Lie groups, Adv. Math. 222 (2009), 1461--1501.